Lev Kreft |
|
The Avant-Garde
is Mainstream |

Marcel Duchamp: Marcel Duchamp author d'une
table, 1997
Lately I have heard the sentence 'The avant-garde has now
become the mainstream' so many times, that I have become rather
suspicious. We could trace its origins back to the sixties
and today it represents a repetition (tragedy of farce?),
as it was written down by the great canonist of modernistic
criticism Clement Greenberg in his essay Avant-Garde Attitudes
(1968) - and yet already this essay is a continuation of the
famous 1939 essay Avant-Garde and Kitsch. His evaluation
of the current artistic movements (which we today normally
call the neo-avant-garde) was that they no longer have a proper
opponent in academic art, because the avant-garde has completely
predominated the artistic scene. And because the avant-garde
remained on the scene with itself, it also applies solely
to itself, therefore plain novelties and spectacularity stepped
in place of qualitative criteria.
One can comprehend that something must be told twice, especially
if there is a period of forty years in between. But when dealing
with reiteration and not merely repetition one has a feeling
that some sort of a forced neurosis is calling a solution
in the form of a diagnosis for help. And the constant talk
about the mainstream avant-garde has already become a sort
of neurosis.
At first glance the statement is a completely normal ascertainment,
which almost should not be discussed. The historical avant-garde
appeared at the beginning of the 20th Century and was well
finished at the latest in the mid thirties. It finished by
the way, as many other things in that period. Following the
peak of radical modernism in the sixties, which supposedly
achieved a level of unchangeable eternity of the end of history,
an artistic movement appeared which was also called the avant-garde.
Whatever it was it was rightfully called the neo-avant-garde,
especially because it had chosen historical avant-garde as
its tradition and because it went into oblivion in the same
way (only a bit faster). At the latest at the beginning of
the eighties it was already announced that the sixties have
finished, and that the attempts to jump into the sky in the
name of utopic beliefs of any kind do not hold any ground
even in art - hence trans-avant-garde, which is a phenomenon
which is (to put it bluntly) a bit over the moon. This was
also one of the reasons why the new wave of attachment to
the historical avant-garde could not have an avant name, but
a retro name. The fact that at the end it arrived at the mainstream
avant-garde is a completely logical step, for at every step
from the historical concept of the avant-garde something went
amiss, and that, which was dismissed at first was its politicality
- its political politicality as well as its aesthetic politicality.
The political politicality of the avant-garde was utopic,
extreme and subversive. The avant-garde was undoubtedly a
political phenomenon, for it appeared publicly, it made its
appearance with political means, and it appeared in groups
- political parties. In his Ph.D. dissertation Miklavž Prosenc
defined the Dada group from Zürich as the following:
1. The members of the group were immigrants and have therefore
found themselves in an extreme situation.
2. As regards the nationalities, origins and professions the
group was a heterogeneous group.
3. It was not comprised only of writers but also of (fine
art) artists.
4. The group's main preoccupation was how to fill a cabaret
programme, which changed often and was comprised of individual
acts.
5. The behaviour of the members was 'extremist', for they
found themselves in an extraordinary situation, caused by
the war and the disintegration of the generally adopted rules.
6. The productions of the members of the group (to the extent
in which they were preserved in writing, whether in the form
of poems or prose text) can be hardly defined as literature,
and not only because they did not want to write 'literature'
and did not want to be 'artists', but because they a priori
placed themselves in opposition to any type of 'art' and with
their actions they were stating a revolt against art and literature.(1)
This was an a priori action against art, and if this was
truly the case this could by no means by an artistic programme,
on the contrary, the avant-garde did not need an artistic
programme, for (as stated by Tristan Tzara(2)) art and culture
of the West did not have to be demolished - they fell to pieces
by themselves. It was merely necessary to draw attention to
the fact that this has happened and trigger the consequences.
Amongst the consequences of the fall of art and culture (which
were based on their own autonomy and which founded this autonomy
in the inherently artistically-cultural superior aim) the
destruction of the autonomy and the transformation to non-artistic
and non-cultural goals was necessary.
Historical avant-garde is a politicisation, it enters the
sphere of politicality as an extreme political party. This
is also the mistake which was made by Peter Bürger in his
otherwise excellent and influential book (Theory of the
Avant-Garde) - he defined the historical avant-garde as
a left wing movement, which was in the 'historical interest'
of the working classes, instead of placing his money on political
extremism as Miklavž Prosenc did. Of course, one could say
that the Zürich Dada is an extreme case, however, it is not
that extreme for the pre-war futurism not to be it's equal
in this sense, let alone the post-war movements in the Soviet
Russia or the defeated Germany.
Where does the political extreme of the avant-gardes lay?
In the fact that they take politics as an (anti) aesthetic
event, process and procession, in which the boarder between
the artificial and real is lost, as well as the boarder between
the artificial and natural - a curved space, in which various
ways of existence of reality, also artistic meet, and in which
it becomes evident that the essence of every reality lies
in its appearance, that nothing is hidden behind the appearance
- except for the appearance itself, which is hidden, even
though it is obvious, behind the strange idea that behind
it lies a hidden and unclear essence.(3)
And where lies the aesthetic politicality of the historical
avant-garde? By all means in its anti-aestheticism and anti-artism,
and at the same time also in the retaliatory efflux of both
anti-postures into life, as stated also by Peter Bürger. One
should differ between anti-aestheticism and anti-artism. As
defined also by the Prague school (which differentiates between
the non-standardised and standardised aesthetics and between
various functions of all linguistic phenomena, including art)
anti-aestheticism is in opposition to the aesthetic function
as a dominant and hegemonistic function in art, which subordinates
all the other and possible artistic functions.(4) We are therefore
dealing with an assault upon the structuralisation of the
meaning values of the artistic work, which is comprised of
various meanings, yet under the domination of the aesthetic
function and in light of the value dictated by its dominant
meaning.
The anti-artistiness is intended for a special position, which
is attributed to art and works of art - this social position
of art and artistic works is (of course) a social expression
of an internal structure of art and works of art, which are,
in the sense of a 'pure aesthetic judgement of taste', organised
as an absolute monarchy.(5) A certain excellency belongs to
art, an excellency out of this world and therefore total autonomy
holds true for it, which means we are not permitted to use
the normal life standards for it - and because it is completely
autonomous and independent from the everyday usefulness, morality
or politicality it can play the role of the saviour in current
conflicts. The domination of the aesthetic function as a function
of 'absolute disinterest' and the total autonomy of art of
course had a social-political function - with these mechanisms
art became the social and political capital of the elite,
which thought of themselves as the aristocrats of the spirit.
The aesthetic politicality of the avant-garde directly and
knowingly attacks and demolishes the position of the aristocrats
of the spirit, who applied themselves with the salvation role
in the human progress and placed themselves in the function
of the arbiter of all spiritual matters. It this fact it is
political as much as it is political in its political politicality.
That is why these two components (the political and aesthetic
politicality) should not be taken as two components which
just happened to meet at the avant-garde. It is true that
we know of a whole line of political politicalities, which
have nothing to do with the aesthetic politicality, and also
the other way round a sufficient number of aesthetic politicalities
could be found (at least within radical modernism), even though
without the group party appearances and so clearly defined
extremisms as at the historic avant-garde. Therefore, nor
one nor the other, but both together are typical for the historical
avant-garde in itself, and both together operate subversively.
This subversion is not a result of political and aesthetic
extremism, but the consequence of the tension, which the togetherness
of the political and aesthetic politicality cause in the political.
In a well organised civil society the state and the society
are appropriately divided as are politics and culture; this
is also the case with the well defined Marxist base and superstructure.
Aesthetics has its privileged place in autonomy, the political
has its privileged place in politics; chosen and elected specialists
deal with one and the other. The subversion of the simultaneous
political and aesthetic politicality, which are both marked
with extremism or with the prefix of anti-politicality and
anti-aestheticism, is found in the fact that it impugns and
shows this division as unbearable.
Hegel states the following: 'The actual idea, the spirit,
which divides itself into two idea spheres of its notion,
the family and civil society, as on its finiteness,
to be from its ideal for itself an infinite actual
ghost, therefore assigns these two spheres the material of
this final actuality, individuals as a mass so that
the assignment is seen by the individual as mediated
through circumstances, self-will and the own choice of their
determination.'(6)
Our everyday conception (we could easily also say ideology)
is that we have a society that is independent from the state
and a state which was created by the society so that its conflicts
and differences could be set straight in an easier manner.
Society therefore elects a state according to its own image.
Hegel is believed to be an idealist and this belief is to
what the ghost that can be found in his state-legal philosophy
is normally ascribed to: the play is entered by a state-making
Spirit which is divided into family and civil society in such
a way that the subjectivation of people from personalities
into subjects seems mediated 'through circumstances, self-will
and own choice of determination'. When Marx started toying
with this point stated by Hegel, he tried to translate it
into prose and turn this prose around in such a way so that
we would reach the true image of things: people who form a
family and a civil society become individuals (subjects) in
this community - and from here onwards they create the state
for themselves. However, in opposition to the usual prose
Hegel is here a materialist and Marx and idealist, for the
Hegelian image of subjectivisation of the individuals into
subjects complies with the actual state of affairs, while
the Marxist (with the exception of Marx' later works) complies
with the ideological image of 'realism'.
For even though it seems and it most probably also is logical,
that at first individuals exist and only then their community,
it is still 'true' that in the modern era the political subjects
are produced by the state and not the other way round, that
the civil society always remains that pre-political background,
from which the state recruits human beings into politicality.
What Marx does with politicality is not to turn Hegel upside
down but he denounces the situation in which we stand on our
heads, with the demand that things should be oriented into
the right direction - society should take hold of the state
and abolish it, and thus leave the political and enter the
actual, human emancipation.
Because of its link between aesthetic and political politicality
(the assault of the autonomy of art with anti-art, political
party extremism with public political appearances) the historical
avant-garde has a different effect: the division on the state
and the civil society, from which a politicality seperated
from aestheticism is born, as well as the process of subjectivising
people into subjects is put under a question mark. The position
of the avant-garde is not a position of the authentic and
natural society in opposition to the corruption of politics
and the state, but also the position of politicality against
the state. This is a civil society movement, which does not
want to be a movement of the civil society, but a political
party with an anti-aesthetic and anti-state programme. Peter
Bürger is correct when he states that the historical avant-garde
stands on the social positions of the proletariat - except
to the extent, that it itself stands on the social positions
of the proletariat, while no one has seen the proletariat
on these positions as yet.
If we take into account the three ways of representation about
which Scott Lash speaks in his Sociology of Postmodernism,
we can place the avant-garde in a position where it is at
the same distance from the centre of modernism as well as
postmodernism. The starting paradigm of representation as
a process, in which the image of reality starts as an image
of a subject (in which reality is 'given') is aesthetic realism.
Lash ascertains that aesthetic realism 'is possible only on
the basis of three previous types of differentiations' in
which the cultural field 'must be divided from the social',
the aesthetic field from the theoretical, and 'the division
of secular culture from religious' is also a necessary precondition.(7)
However, the most important precondition in order for this
three fold differentiation to work at all is that it remains
invisible and unproblematic. Between the signifier, the signified
and the referent there should be no disharmony, the way from
a thing-in-itself through the subject-for-us to the image
of the object or sign for the object is smooth and does not
have any hurdles or problems. With modernism and postmodernism
the situation changes and the realistic lightness of representation
is turned into an issue, however, this takes place at two
different ends: 'The difference is in the fact that modernism
understands representations as some sort of a problem, while
postmodernism makes an issue out of reality itself.'(8)
Modernism abolishes the belief into a single image of the
world, i.e. an image which through a convention is believed
to be 'realistic', a similar image and an appropriate picture,
and researches the alternative methods of representation.
At this it does not question what should be represented in
the representation - there are only numerous ways of depicting
and the realistic way of depiction loses its absolute validity.
Postmodernism starts the way at its starting point: that,
which we believe to be an unproblematic process of presentation
and depiction, and which experiences various ways of presentation
and depiction in realism, is also in itself merely a convention.
'The real world', the world of concrete facts which should
be represented and commented upon in a right way is not the
beginning or the cause of various procedures of depicting
and marking the world but a result and a consequence of these
procedures.
The avant-garde with its historic procedures of abolishing
art in life and a simultaneous revolt that it wants to make
in life itself, does in fact use both approaches, the modernistic
and postmodernistic, but both only to a certain extent. In
realism art is an autonomous sphere in the sense of a sphere,
therefore it depicts reality; in modernism art is absolutely
autonomous, for it is art itself that is the only true reality
which gives the character of reality and with this the human
reality to all other spheres - this is where the idea of the
religion of art lies in; for the avant-garde in its radical
phase art as either a reflection or the only right world is
what should be left behind, deserted or demolished, so that
no two stones stay together. Reality is somewhere else, in
life, which is shown on one side as modernity of a new industrial
revolution (big city life, the factory rhythm, electric power,
the car chaos and flying, etc.), while on the other hand,
as a bad infinity of constant new failures and increasingly
fast changing and starting anew from scratch, which should
be finished. For the avant-garde the slogan that art should
be left for life does not mean that we should return to the
direct and unproblematic reality, on the contrary: the most
problematic is reality itself, which should be overthrown
and turned around. Life, into which it would wish to enter
is something which as such, does not yet exist, and that is
why the avant-garde is utopic. Finally, the conflict between
the Bolshevik central committee and the Russian avant-garde
originated from this. After the conflict the communist party
took over the leading role amongst the proletariat and later
on it took over the leading role in the new socialist culture.
The party ascertained that the heroic age is over, and that
the time has come for everybody to return to their natural
chores: the party should rule, the society should change and
produce. Artists should produce works of art and at this follow
the political plans of the leaders of the revolutionary transformation
- especially due to the fact that the world revolution did
not seem to appear, and the Soviet Russia was alone and surrounded
by enemies. If everybody would not take care of their chores,
the land of hope for the entire humanity would fail, that
is why discipline with the division of work was of utmost
importance. The avant-gardists attacked especially the division
of work (through which they were forced to be 'societal')
into the differentiation of chores, which took away any autonomous
function within the politicality. The central committee designated
art and especially the avant-garde a place in representing
the world within the frames of artistic autonomy, which accepted
the party representation of the world as 'reality'. From all
of the artistic elite of the time only the avant-garde accepted
the party representation of the world as 'reality', but at
the same time it was the only movement that did not accept
the division into the political and social sphere, which within
the social sphere defined the position of the artistic autonomy
to all artistic activities and tendencies including the avant-garde.
The dispute between the modernists and the party was about
the freedom of artistic expression, the dispute between the
avant-garde and the party regarded the freely accessible and
equal for all revolutionary politicality. The modernists did
not need to be differentiated they only needed to be subordinated,
for differentiation was already their natural environment
- the avant-gardists did not need to be subordinated, they
only needed to be differentiated, i.e. placed back - into
art.
To a certain extent the neo-avant-garde by itself de-politicised
the historical avant-garde. This was mainly performed through
the fact that it made the avant-garde it's own tradition and
thus institutionalised it. However, the neo-avant-garde had
it's own politicality in which the division on the (dirty)
politicality and savour sociality was already dominant. The
manner of the struggle of town guerrillas and terrorism, and
the manner of the struggle with the retreat into the new spirituality,
showed (in two extreme ways) that the neo-avant-garde which
belonged to such movements according to its own ideologies
and often also with its striving and public appearances, presented
emancipation as an abolishment of the political within the
social.(9)
All of the realistically existing ideological systems representing
the correctly organised reality pushed the historical avant-garde
back into artistic autonomy. This means that alongside Nazism
and Stalinism, which both used also extreme violence this
was also done by fascism and liberalism, which were less violent
- although not always. In its stronghold there is therefore
also something much more dangerous than wrong slogans, i.e.
the approach itself, which does not fit any of the political
systems of modernistic control of the societal. In the position
of the historical avant-garde lurks a view which reveals that
society is a handy product of that political structure which
created also artistic autonomy as a pleasant organised residence
from which art is not supposed to enter the dirty and dangerous
world. And it is not a fact that the state should be abolished
so the society could come to the power, rather one has to
operate politically in order for the society to be abolished.
In the relation to the postmodern indifference the avant-garde
political stand is unpleasant because it can not declare the
autonomy of art and society as some sort of simulacra, which
seemed to be reality, but now we have seen through them. Representations
in fact do have political power and this is why the avant-gardists
demand that art should meet life and not the deduction that
these representations are something weak, which could be deducted
from the ascertainment that representations do not show 'reality'.
The German ideologists must be mistaken when they think that
one can learn how to swim by forgetting gravity - and in a
similar manner the postmodernists imagine that we will forever
step out of the representation combats and enter the end of
history by forgetting 'reality'.
In the neo-avant-garde and in postmodernism the historical
politicality of the avant-garde was de-politicised and one
could almost say nationalised, and in this way the 20th Century
avant-garde could enter the cultural institutions, which take
care of the artistic values of the past. The historical avant-garde
really did not make it, as stated by Bürger, and in the beginning
of the 1930's it was defeated, however, from this defeat the
way did not lead into institutions but into oblivion. The
institutionalisation of the avant-gardes could be dealt with
only when the historical avant-garde became a thing of the
past. And it became a thing of the past when it was
generally accepted, that the sell by date of its concept of
aesthetisation of politics and politisation of aesthetics,
was long overdue.
When we say today that the 'avant-garde became mainstream'
we do not think only that the historical avant-garde has become
a part of the great art collection of the past, where it found
its place next to modernism as well as within modernism, even
to an extent where the division between the avant-garde and
modernism becomes invisible.(10) It is aimed at the fact that
the world can not be changed with works of art, however shocking
and exciting these works of art may be. And at this the arm
is critically waved over two types of 'political' art, which
are the most profiled at this moment in time. The first type
is art, which serves the community and its needs to create
self-images and images for others (today this is usually called
identity and it belongs alongside the 'Indian', 'post-colonial'
and other necessary for the construction of one's identity
likeness) as well as all of that that could be seen at the
Manifesta and in ŠKUC: sentimental Hollywood mourning image
or the self-image of Bosnia during the war and after it, which
supposedly represents engaged art. The other type of 'political'
art is that, which literally or in a figurative meaning of
the word acts as a wholesome designer of barricades and weapons,
with which the anti-capitalist movement from Seattle to Quebec
is attacking global capitalism.
This type is romantically pathetic, such as for example the
Democracy exhibition, set up last year at the Royal College
of Art in London, which the Art Monthly critic JJ Charlesworth
recognised as an artistic parallel to the Labour day demonstrations
and the soiling of Churchill's statue, and already with the
first sentence rejected it as cheap fashion: 'Social conscience
and political engagement in art is back in the mainstream.'(11)
Thus he brings the critical analysis to the conclusion, that
with this mainstream politisation of art we have only gained
a therapeutic self-expression of people within a society with
no alternative and artistic autonomy without any art.
Of course, this is exactly what the historical avant-garde
claimed to hold true for the concept of autonomy and the concept
of society. That, which was politically subversive, for certain
was not serving the artistic ideals (which are not from this
world) neither the transition into a social movement which
would serve the correct political ideals.
Today's art is not subversive? Art can not even be subversive.
Today's avant-garde is not aesthetically digestible? The avant-garde
can not at all be aesthetically digestible. Political subversion
is always aesthetically indigestible and socially useless.
Whoever is looking for it in the mainstream, will never find
it.
1. Miklavž Prosenc, Die Dadaisten in Zürich,
H. Bouvier u. CO. Verlag, Bonn, 1967, pp. 5-6.
2. Georges Hugnet, L'aventure Dada (1916-1922), Paris,
1957, p. 7 of the Tzara foreword to the book: 'Dada a essayé
non pas autant de détrouire l'art et littérature, que l'idée
qu'on s'en était faite'; Quoted by Miklavž Prosenc, p. 66.
3. This is also described in my study 'Jedermann sein eigner
Fussball', Estetika in poslanstvo, Znanstveno in publicistično
središče, Ljubljana, 1994, pp. 75 - 79.
4. Jan Mukarovski, Struktura pesničkog jezika (The structure
of poetry language), Zavod za udžbenike i nastavna sredstva,
Belgrade, 1985 (especially the studies on the aesthetics of
language and poetic language), and Jan Mukarovski, Struktura,
funkcija, znak, vrednost (Structure, function, sign,
value), Nolit, Belgrade, 1987 (especially 'Pesničko delo
kao skup vrednosti' ('A work of poetry as a total of values'),
pp. 238-244).
5. Theodor Lipps, 'O formi estetske apercepcije' (On the form
of aesthetic aperception), Filozofija na maturi 1/2-2000,
pp. 14-19; 'What we see, is thus taken exactly as a double
subordination and not merely a single, on each and every occasion.
Also the relation between the elements and the whole is already
a subordination
and
the whole is once more subordinated
to one single element and within it the remaining elements
become factors. I normally define this double subordination
as monarchic' subordination.' (1902).
6. Georg Wilhelm Frierich Hegel, Basic lines of legal philosophy
or Natural law and civics in a draft outline, &262;
quoted from the Slovene translation in Karl Marx - Friedrich
Engels, Collected works I. 'The critic of Hegel's state
law' (manuscript from 1843), Cankarjeva Založba, Ljubljana,
1969, p. 59.
7. Scott Lash, Sociology of Postmodernism (Slovene
translation), Znanstveno in publicistično središče, Ljubljana,
1993, p. 16.
8. Ibid., p. 22.
9. This is also why ustvarjanje antipolitike (creating
anti-politics) by Tonči Kuzmanić can also be read as a
criticism of the 'social movements' in the 1960's and 'civil
rights movements' of the 1980's, even though it directly speaks
only about what 'was pushed out if not completely destroyed
by the society and social sciences with their intensive, almost
colonial brutal development, i.e. from the standing point
of the politics and political' (Tonči Kuzmanić, Ustvarjanje
antipolitike, Znanstveno in publicistično središče, Ljubljana,
1996, p. 9).
10. That is the review of 20th Century art, which was set
as an installation for the opening of Tate Modern in London
last year: the entire 20th Century is compromised and synthesised
as an entity, from which the avant-garde as a special entity
or at least an autonomous part can not be seen any more.
11. JJ Charlesworth, 'Mayday! May Day!', Art Monthly,
London, May 2000 No. 236, p. 13.
Lev Kreft: philospher and sociologist, lecturer of aesthetics
at the Faculty of Arts in Ljubljana, President of the Slovenian
Society of Aesthetics, President of the Peace Institute Board,
Ljubljana.
|